October 7, 16-17.30 h.,Erasmusbuilding 14.11
Åshild Næss, University of Nijmegen
Abstract: It
is well known that in English, Dutch, and many other languages, both European
and otherwise, the verb 'eat' has the peculiarity of being ''ambitransitive'',
that is, it is equally grammatical with a direct object (I'm eating a sandwich) as without one
(I'm eating). What is perhaps less
well known is that this is only one manifestation of a broader tendency for
verbs meaning 'eat' to occur in formally intransitive constructions crosslinguistically.
In some languages, 'eat' is a so-called extended intransitive verb, taking
an oblique rather than a direct object; in others, it is simply intransitive,
and must undergo morphological derivation if it is to be used with a direct
object; in yet others, it occurs in causative constructions normally reserved
for intransitive verbs, and so on.
Current theories of the semantic properties of transitive
constructions have no obvious way of explaining these patterns. According
to the generally accepted notion of a transitive construction as one referring
to an event involving a volitonally causing agent and a highly affected patient
participant, 'eat' should be a highly transitive verb, and in fact is treated
as such in a number of accounts such as Andrews (1985). It has been argued
that the relevant property is that of telicity, intransitive uses of 'eat'
being necessarily atelic; but this is not in fact the case, as can be seen
from English sentences such as I ate in
five minutes before rushing off to work.
In this talk, I will argue that the semantic property responsible
for the recurrent use of 'eat' in intransitive constructions is that of that
of having an affected agentargument
(Saksena 1980). A verb like ‘eat’ not only affects its patient, it also has
a consistent and salient effect on its agent, and it is this latter effect
which generally constitutes the motivation of the agent for performing the
act. It is this fact which distinguishes 'eat' from fully transitive verbs
like 'kill' or 'break', which typically affect their patient only.
Standard accounts of transitivity refer only to affectedness
of the patient and to properties such as volitionality and animacy of the
agent, and so have no way of explaining how affectedness of the agent would
render a verb less semantically transitive. I will argue that a prototypical
transitive clause must be defined in terms of maximal semantic opposition of its arguments:
if it is a defining characteristic of an agent argument that it volitionally
instigates the action, and of the patient that it is affected by the action,
then it is also characteristic of the patient that it is not volitional and instigating, and of
the agent that it is nonaffected.
In other words, a prototypical transitive clause has one volitional instigator
and one affected argument, and any deviation from this maximal semantic distinction
between arguments leads to a less semantically transitive clause, which may
be reflected formally in the encoding of such a clause differently from clauses
which doshow such maximal semantic
opposition of arguments.